#under capitalist definitions of productivity btw
Explore tagged Tumblr posts
Text
really the problem i'm having with most of these tula fics is the fact that i do always write Tula as some level of Crazy, but then the idea of having to go through and tag that and implicitly introduce the DSM into stoat society conceptually pisses me off so bad that i don't want to make the effort to do it at all, actually. so that's why they're all hanging out in my WIP folder
#N posts stuff#LOOK. it's important that Tula is 'Crazy' and not actually like. thinking on the same wavelength as the rest of her family#but then i think about it and the idea of STOATS having a sane/insane dichotomy makes me like.... mmmmmmmmmm#generally speaking i really make no effort to Specifically 'diagnose' a character with any one specific label.#i'll use 'autism' a lot granted but i keep it vague outside of htat. which is why i tag Evan as 'schizo-spectrum' and not anything else#and why i use the tag 'brainweird' above all else#and it's because the hyperspecific labels of the DSM are - broadly speaking - unhelpful and not even particularly descriptive#having Delusions does not actually tie you into any one diagnosis. or even one at all. some doctors will happily tell you that#if you are delusional / have hallucinations but they don't distress you that bad or interfere with your life a lot then you're#actually functionally Neurotypical bc so many diagnostics function Explicitly on a scale of dysfunction/distress#under capitalist definitions of productivity btw#and not anything else. these terms have Meaning in that they are Defined but also they are meaningless in that like.#you can argue that fucking anyone can fit a diagnostic label if you're feeling uncharitable enough. psychologists do it all the time#i can talk about this extensively and i don't want to. needless to say it makes me angry and i'm annoyed by it all.#broadly speaking i DO use tags on ao3 entirely for Search functionality. if other crazy people are looking for fic about crazy#people (like me) i want us to be able to find them. unfortunately the application of them here make me want to bite someone to death
1 note
¡
View note
Note
Omg, I'm no longer under my mom's insurance because I'm 26 and I went to a visit my doctor last month for a checkup. It was a simple visit, nothing else and yet that visit costs $500. I fucking hate how going to the doctor is expensive.
A lot of Americans are literally so brainwashed they think the current healthcare system is acceptable and that healthcare âisnât a right.â They donât even realize that we already pay more than most countries with our shitty private insurance system.
I personally just think itâs fundamentally immoral and fucked up for your ability to get healthcare to be largely tied to your ability to be employable and productive in a capitalist society. Itâs one of the most ableist things I can think of. Btw, before anyone calls me a âjobless Commie,â I HAVE a job with good healthcare benefits but many others donât. And still more are trapped in crappy jobs they hate because they canât afford to lose their benefits.
The older I get the more I think itâs intentional. Iâm not really a conspiracy theorist but those in power definitely benefit from Americans being workhorses who canât afford to stop working or else they lose their ability to stay healthy without going into massive debt.
30 notes
¡
View notes
Text
Socialism Smocialism
Iâm sick to death of hearing this term tossed around by people who have no idea what it means. To the (deliberately?) uninformed and misinformed it is just the âbogeymanâ that supposedly stands opposed to everything America does and has. Any real definition of socialism is complex; there are market and non-market based systems, some nationalistic, others international. And within each of those ownership of the means of production (as economists call it) may be public (government), by employees, or even private equity but regulated, and there are even more possible combinations. The point is, that there is no major industrial country (including the USA) that doesnât have some âsocialisticâ elements in its economy, and these tend to be very popular with the people.
Oddly enough, those who are often the most vocal are the very people who would benefit from most of the âsocialistâ programs, and those whose taxes might increase because of them are willing to spend way more than their taxes would increase to oppose such plans. They can argue that they are supporting a principle, a sort of âdominoâ or âslippery slopeâ theory, but it is still a foolish waste of money. But again, those who have gotten their wealth through inheritance, good luck or even one brilliant idea, are more likely to go with the âlow riskâ approach to maintaining it. They like power, and power likes stability.
To put it briefly, the so called âidealâ of a purely free market, laissez faire capitalist economic system very quickly devolves into a group of monopolistic companies with little to no incentive to allow any development or improvement in their area of influence, unless they can control and significantly benefit from it.
So-called socialist programs are most likely to be needed and implemented in situations of basic needs and services where there is little to no profit, especially without leaving out a large segment of the people. Health care quickly comes to mind as one of these areas.
Criticisms of social healthcare plans usually dredge up a few examples of poorly designed or poorly implemented plans. Critics talk about ârationedâ care, long waits to see a doctor etc. But wait, the insurance companies here already do that with pre-authorizations your doctor must get from them before certain treatments. If you are in an HMO type plan your doctor may already be limited in the amount of time he can spend with each patient on average, or by diagnosis. And then there is the whole issue of whether or not the insurance company will even insure you, or at least at a rate most people could afford. When you look at the whole picture honestly, some bureaucrat in charge of my healthcare doesnât look much different, let alone worse, than some profit maximizing insurance company.
Congratulations to the decades of conservative liars, mythmakers and dissemblers â you have successfully muddied the waters in this area enough to confuse the public. BTW if you support this unilateral âanti-socialistâ nonsense, and you are not one of these millionaires or in their hire, then you are a dupe who has been conned into doing their work for them for free. How does that feel?
People think socialism means limited choice, but thatâs not necessarily so. Having a real choice is not possible when people sell plans where they make their most money by NOT fulfilling their promises.
Here is another false line of reasoning they like to use; personal responsibility. Insurance, by its very nature, is intended to provide payments to some in a group (but not to all) based on what was needed (covered under the policy). By distorting and misrepresenting the concept of self-reliance and responsibility the insurance companies have pushed us closer to simply paying for all of our medical expenses ourselves (but through premiums), with the only alleged advantage being supposed discounts on drugs and services; discounts from artificially high prices (like the old âmanufacturersâ suggested retail priceâ, MSRP).
In summary, âsocialismâ isnât near the bogeyman, or problem, that itâs been made out to be. It exists in many forms and the right forms, in the right areas is simply humane, and reasonable â while its opposite (unregulated âcapitalismâ) is a cheap justification for writing off segments of the population as simply â not worthyâ of basic services.
3 notes
¡
View notes
Text
Why animals donât form value, although they deserve justice
A very wise friend of mine and an animal rights advocate wrote to me after reading my last post to ask me whether or not a dog produces value when he and the dog play together as equals, each knowing that they have the freedom to exit the relation if they stop feeling that the relation is enjoyable. Itâs an interesting question, and I am lucky to have a friend who would be able to patiently pick apart a sub-par argument, so I took the time to write a very precise reply. I decided to post it here as well since it may be interesting.
///
I would say that the difference in that scenario is that you and the dog arenât engaged in an exchange of labor in a market, which are the only conditions under which value exists for Marx (widespread exchange of the privately-produced products of labor, produced by people who at least have formal autonomy from one another). I would say that, in your case, the fact that you arenât working is primary and implies the second condition (that there is no market). It seems to me that you and your dog are not trading equal amounts of work and thereby dividing up your total ability to work on the basis of equality.* To me, neither of you is working in the sense that neither of you is doing something in which, whether you enjoy the process or not, the outcome rather than the process is definitely the ultimate purpose (whether you intend to keep or trade the product being irrelevant). Iâm not sure if thatâs a great definition of the work/play distinction, but thatâs the best way to put it I can think of right now. Going further, I would say that dogs are currently not capable of engaging in the human social division of labor, not because they couldnât physiologically replace some of the work that humans currently do (e.g. they could probably pull a plow), but because they donât engage with people in a way where they demand social recognition as equal and where they also demand, as part of that overall demand for recognition, some normal market price for their product; if animals have to be forced with overt physical coercion, thatâs outside of a ânormal market relationshipâ in some meaningful ways,** and so the animal canât (even if they want to) secure anything approximating a normal price for their product. But even if itâs voluntary�� letâs say even if animals are glad for some exercise and work willingly (not sure how often this really happens, but it could) â they donât seem to have (presently) the social capacity to demand that if they work, they receive the ânormalâ market-price for their work, that is, what other people receive for the same amount of work (I guess, at the margin, a donkey that is happy for some light exercise might balk at another donkey receiving more food in return for work, but I think an animal has to, at a minimum, have to have the cognitive capacity to a. connect the amount of food that they get with their work and b. know to say âI will withdraw this work if I am not fed moreâ; even if they do, c. because they are at present the legal property of people, they canât really act to secure this result, but basically all people in capitalist society at least have some sense of what is normal pay for a given job and they have the formal freedom to secure that pay).*** Iâm not sure that any non-human animals besides monkeys have that capacity; I do think, from my fairly limited knowledge of monkeys, that there are probably meaningful senses in which they could someday potentially form a part of human society, but I donât think weâre at that point yet. Iâm not sure whether monkeys would choose to have regular interactions with people if they could freely so choose. I would definitely say, at present, that even those smartest monkeys are not interacting with people in a way that is 1) truly formally-autonomous, 2) involves work-like activities, and 3) involves them being socially-calculating enough to count as participants in a human division of laborâbut I think that they probably could do those things, although I donât know that that would be good for them.
So, I would say, to the extent that you and a dog play consensually, youâre engaging freely or autonomously with one another, but I would still say that 1) you arenât working (because both of you do the activity primarily for its own sake)*** and 2) you arenât working in a way where 3) you work with the understanding that there is a normal price for your work, which price you can 4) use market tools (the decision to freely enter and exit contracts) to secure. Given that dogs are, after millennia of domestication, better off with humans than without us, it strikes me as a relation of care and love but not one of equals, primarily because I donât think dogs can want that and can act to secure that (and probably wouldnât want that, much like children for the most part probably donât really want to be treated as equal to adults). I would say that, in general, for its physical work to be value-forming (that is, for it to form part of the social division of human labor through market-exchange), I would say that the animal would need not only to be able to exit but to be concerned to equalize their reward from working with the reward others receive for a similar amount of work and they would need to be so-concerned because they depend on the market for the things they consider necessary for normal life. On my read of Marx, value just is the human division of labor effected through the market; itâs similar to the âlower phase of communist societyâ in that work that is concretely different is brought into a relationship of equality because people are able to evaluate whether two kinds of work are basically equal in terms of intensity and to act so that the products of two days of the same work are regularly exchanged for each other (in capitalism, they do this by deciding what a normal amount of money for a job is vis-a-vis what other jobs pay for similar work; in socialism, this is a conscious group decision; the key bad thing about capitalism is that because most people lack the means to realize their own labor at the prevailing standard of technology, they sell what they actually have, which is not their work but their ability to work).
I hope that wasnât too long/repetitive. It was a really interesting question to think about and it took me a while to think of the answer I would give. Thank you for asking it. BTW, there is some writing on Marx and animals that I know of. I donât know if I would endorse it, but I know Ted Bentonâs work is focused on this. I briefly read a reply to his work from someone whose work I like named Lawrence Wilde (the paper he wrote is titled ââThe creatures, too, must become freeâ: Marx and the Animal/Human Distinctionâ and itâs good).
BTW, Marx describes this aspect of capitalist realityâpeople coming together to exchange their products on the basis of how long it took to make themâas a surface appearance only; itâs not that capitalism is the same thing as a society of simple producers who all own their own means of production and trade in a market, but capitalism is superficially similar to that hypothetical society and parts of capitalism that are important, if superficial, are easier to describe if that kind of society is described before the concept of class is introduced; Marxâs value-theory is laid out in Capital before the concept of class (or even of capital) is discussed systematically. I think, most crucially, he wants to start with this picture because his analysis of exploitation depends on the notion that workers are paid the value (socially necessary labor-time) of what they have to sell, which is their capacity to work; in other words, he shows that even with perfect markets, people can be exploited because at a certain level of social productivity, most people have the intrinsic capacity to work for longer than they need to produce the goods needed to enjoy some socially-minimal standard of living and they have an incentive to do so because capitalists have a relative monopsony on the means of production.
** Marx abstracts from this overt physical coercion even though it has obviously formed part of capitalism for a long period of time, mostly because heâs challenging capitalism on its own terms so that people canât say âwell, sure, capitalism currently involves overt physical coercion of market participants [e.g., in the case of slavery] but eventually it wonâtâ.
*** BTW, the rub, for Marx, is that the price of proletariansâ labor turns out not to be the value of their work per se but the commodity that they actually, in reality, possess and can sell, which is simply their capacity to work) to secure that pay
*** I donât mean this to be tautological; I think that peopleâs behaviors significantly change if they see an activity as requisite vs. recreational, even if people often find joy in doing requisite thingsâprimarily that, for people who arenât âindependently wealthyâ, to the extent that you need to do requisite things (or to work) in order to survive, you canât work sheerly on your own terms (e.g., if you love teaching and would do it anyways if you had no income constraints, as I think we both might, this nevertheless doesnât mean that itâs easy for us to opt out of suboptimal teaching arrangements in the case that we do need to do it to earn a living).
0 notes
Text
Manufacturing SMART Vaginas: Cyborgs And The Future of The Ubiquitous
This is an old piece of work that I reworked. I got rid of the bits I didnât think was relevant while retaining some older parts. Itâs safe to say that while discussing Haraway and the Cyborg Manifesto, that a bio-essentialist critique would emerge. I tried my very best to bear that in mind while I was re-working this essay (that I wrote more than a year ago as a baby feminist btw). I understand that the very definition of vagina is extremely essentialist and therefore very problematic. However, writing about the reproduction of machinist and masculine interpretations of âwomanâ, essentialist language was unfortunately what followed.
If there are any womxn or non-binary trans folx out there reading this and have some tips on how to write in a more anti-essentialist, de-centralizing manner whilst engaging in topics like the vagina, please do drop me a message. I would really love that <3. That being said, enjoy reading.
The political, the social, and the body are topics very often undervalued in technological advances. That is because it runs counter to what the public understands as the purpose and use of technology â being that it will elevate humanity to a position devoid of all social problems.
There is an assumption that the ultimate goal for the advancement of technology is to somehow alleviate labour â labour within the workforce, labour of the personal, and essentially the labour of our bodies. It is assumed that the progression of technology will and can, quite magically, create a world in which all of our problems will disappear. Quite contrarily, the acceleration of technology appears to only be the means to a utopian solutionist end. When in reality, technology shrinks labour into extremely limiting and constricting gendered boxes; quite the opposite of what it aims to solve.
The perception that the elements of body, society, and technology live in distinction from one another, and from politics of gender, are inherently problematic, as is the idea that one is capable of absolving the other. Our understanding of technology as a solution is ultimately part of the wider problem. As long as this notion remains uncontested, social and political issues will remain sidelined in technological approaches, and will continue to perpetuate a form of invisible labour on our bodies, and reproduce these normative gendered approaches within new technology.
SMART Janet Smart
Sarah Kember describes this very paradigm colliding gender with the technological world as one that is ubiquitous, so far as to link womenâs bodies directly to its ubiquity: everywhere, and everyWEAR; constantly subjected to scrutiny, regulation, and self regulation, to produce ever more productive and ever more âperfectâ versions of ourselves through devices we come in contact with. Kember images an indistinguishable relationship within the gendered realm of ubiquitous technology and female bodies.
Describing Janet Smart in her book âiMediaâ, Janet Smart being a metaphor for the many, if not all ubiquitous women in the world, Kember refers to SMART technology as a medium of feminized labour. She connects the labour of Janet as a [female body] merging with the environment around her. Janet moves from her SMART bed, to her SMART kitchen, to her SMART toilet, where thereâs a SMART mirror inscribed with a digitised to-do list full of unsurprisingly heteronormative tasks ahead of her i.e. shopping and baking. All this and more before Janet even gets to brush her teeth or make her morning coffee.
Even though the idea of having a choice is apparent, and Janet is presented as a creature of independence, it is an illusion of agency that has been painted for her by automation and SMART tech. She is inevitably being manipulated by her environment and subsequently policed by it. She alters her behaviour throughout the day, restructuring her manipulation into a facade of the agency of productiveness (Kember, 2015:81). This is labour,Â
âJanet doesnât get to choose, as she lives through her day, she becomes an agent of her own reconstitution as a political subjectâ (YouTube, 2017).
While the idea of a ubiquitized SMART Janet, subjugated to producing feminized labour via her body does indeed seem like a thing that has been born out of modern technological advancements, it is certainly not new. Neither is it solely tied to contemporary automation and technology.
The Paradigm of Hysteria
During the 1800 â 1900s, women who experienced symptoms ranging from anxiety and irritability to vaginal lubrication and abdominal pains were often subjected to the diagnosis of Hysteria. This was a condition in which doctors believed only the interventions by androcentric and heterocentric medicine could absolve. Such interventions were not only bodily intrusive, but were often focused on the âânormalâ het-erosexual [âŚ] penetration of the vaginaâ (Maines, 2001:23) as a form of treatment or cure.
The diagnosis of hysteria in women in 1800s was so widespread that physicians began employing the use of technology in order to help relieve themselves of the fatigue caused by giving therapeutic massages. Technology became a way for doctors, or therapists, to expedite the process of inducing, or producing a female orgasm. Incorporating technology into the practice, many of the treatments evolved from manually administered massages to include hydro massages to the womb, clitoral electromechanical vibrators, and penetrative dildos. These apparatuses were designed to alleviate the laborious task of producing a female orgasm, gesturing to notion that women were in essence, incapable of being an autonomous agent to their own pleasure and understanding their own bodies.
The medical world was turning to new technology to administer a wide array of treatments for what they believed were symptoms of chronic hysteria, to which the cure was to produce an orgasm (ibid:22-25). Thus became the most widely understood, ubiquitized, and embodied technological use against the female body, routinely exercised through the most politicised location on the female body â the vagina. This phenomenon was later defined by Foucault as the âhysterisization of womenâs bodiesâ, referring to the disease paradigm that framed female bodies as one constantly regarded as highly sexual and an object of public and medical knowledge, as well as a matter requiring control (Foucault, 1990:11).
Technological advancements made to treat hysteria during this period of âhysterisizationâ continued to proliferate, with an array of devices spilling out of the medical market made to tackle the various challenges posed by the perceived failing capabilities of a functional orgasming female body.
In the 1900s, Freud concluded that women were only capable of two types of orgasms, a vaginal orgasm and a clitoral orgasm, the latter of which was deemed by him as âimmatureâ and âinfantileâ. He asserted that women who could not achieve, or produce an orgasm through vaginal penetration were stunted as result of arrested development in the juvenile stage (Freud,1975). This became a widely accepted notion for which set hysteria treatment, and the technology that accompanied it, on a new trajectory, one for which we now know was a pseudo claim to a psychoanalytic and scientific revelation.
Nevertheless, Freudâs ârevelationâ in psychoanalysis resulted in a fundamental shift within hysterical treatment. More focus was thereby placed on the vagina as the appropriate contributor to an orgasm, and technological approaches to treating hysteria began to evolve to fit that shape as well. The conclusion made by Freud created the socialized belief that female sexuality and the only acceptable route to female pleasure was situated strictly in the vagina through penetration. Hence turning the role of the clitoris in the understanding of female orgasms and arousal into one that was largely misunderstood and disregarded. The vagina became the sole vessel to which hysteria treatments were to be administered.
Machine\Vagina
Much like the labouring, ubiquitous, female body as described by Kember, the technology that arose during the âperiod of hysterisizationâ is similar. When measuring the efficiency of the technology for hysterical treatment, the characteristic merging of capabilities between the vagina, its ability to produce orgasms, and itâs aiding technological counterpart is apparent.
The productivity of the machine administering the orgasm is measured hand in hand with the efficiency of the vagina that is able to produce one. The interwoven language of capabilities between technology and vagina thereby becomes almost indiscernible, where the description of one can no longer be distinguished from the other; the machine that labours well is only as good as a vagina that orgasms efficiently. This is further articulated in Mainesâs book where the language describing optimal productivity of the vagina at the time was attributed to an almost factory-like commodity, outlined by itâs ability to churn out orgasms in aÂ
âless capital intensive[âŚ] more reliable, portableâ manner (Maines, 2001:30).
It is therefore understood that within the paradigm of hysterisization, the female vagina is simply another component to which capitalistic mediums and technology can, and will ultimately relieve. Whereby if the sole goal is to produce an orgasm, then the machine, already exemplary in its form, will facilitate that goal until it is achieved. However, it is only under capitalist masculine interpretations can this happen.
The woman who is unable to have a vaginal orgasm through penetration is perceived as inadequate, a product of her own affliction; immature, unhuman, hysterical and faulty. She is to work harder, just as a machine, to diminish the bodyâs hysterisization, and to induce in herself a vaginal orgasm. She is to continuously labour, through her vagina, an ever more flawless, ever more effective version of her orgasming self, without ever engaging with the very organ on her body that delivers orgasmic pleasure â the clitoris. And if she fails, she is just as faulty as the machine that fails along with her.
This collision between body and machine is ubiquitous in its development. Women were unconsciously producing, through machine intervention, a labouring vagina intertwined with its physical and social environment, capable of readjusting itself to mitigate hysteria diagnosis within the body and away from medical damnation. The woman ultimately doesnât have a role in mediating her own sexual pleasure, and as Kember describes, is turned into an agent of her own political and social subjugation.
Hysterization Within New Technology
While hysteria treatments no longer exist, and the violence of hysterisization has since been forgotten by the medical community and the public, it appears that the technological paradigm that had attempted to âcurbâ hysteria diagnosed in women have not been at all eradicated. But rather, repositioned from the hands of doctors, and subsequently placed in the hands of women themselves.
There is a growing emergence of SMART technology that exists today that supposedly allows women a new sense of closeness with their bodies through datarizing and monitoring algorithms. Connected via applications on their SMART phones and other devices, the experience of interacting with such SMART technology is often presented as highly personalized; where women can hold the reigns of technology quite literally, in the palms of their hands.
Such SMART technologies range from sex toy apps to period tracking apps, and stake a claim on the ability to improve the sexual and bodily health of women. They are often marketed with an emphasis on offering women the ease, convenience, and agency to use such apps to their own satisfaction and benefit. However, these âbenefitsâ only remain to serve as a perpetuating structure for technology that surpasses women themselves in understanding the capabilities of their own bodies.
The notion of SMART technology first became prominent in the 1990s, originally a diagnostic method developed to cope with computer failure. SMART, or âSelf-Monitoring Analysis and Reporting Technologyâ was categorized as technology that was able to predict computer failure and produce a diagnostic report before it happened as a preventive measure. According to the Encyclopaedia of Information Science and Technology, smart technology refers toÂ
âtechnologies (includes physical and logical applications in all formats) that are capable to adapt automatically and modify behavior to fit environment [âŚ] is also capable of learning, [âŚ] using experience to improve performance, anticipating, thinking and reasoning about what to do next, with the ability to self-generate and self sustainâ (Igi-global.com, 2017).
It is under the capacity of âbehaviour developmentâ and âperformance improvementâ do these SMART devices continue to exist. But only in bid to alleviate female bodies from its perceived bodily limitations, and to elevate it to that of which is recognized as socially adequate and functional. It disregards the autonomy of women in defining what is a functional body is for and within themselves.
The technological endeavour to meet these developmental goals fail however, to consider that when capabilities of SMART get inscribed with the intentions of capitalism, a system that ensures the economic profit and political gain of those in power, it inevitably reproduces existing, damaging gender normative and heteronormative models.
SMART technology, while striving to counter real problems faced by women such as infertility, sexual non-pleasure, bladder control, and recovery from childbirth, continue to sustain an incredibly disconcerting sociopolitical dimension parallel to that of the hysterisization period.
The Elvie
One embodiment of such SMART technology is the Elvie, an award-winning pelvic floor exercise tracking device. Built to be small and discreet, it resembles a streamline silicon pod, similar to the size of a pebble. It is capable of feeding and receiving strings of information to, from, and between human and machine, as well as process data within itself. When inserted into the vagina, the Elvie sits inside of the body, and engages with the user via Bluetooth. In the form of an app on oneâs iOS or Android phone, one is then able to play a series of âgamesâ ranging in difficulty involving an on-screen gem.
The SMART functions of an Elvie work by utilizing the pelvic floor muscles in the userâs vagina. Once the pod is placed in oneâs vagina, it registers the force applied by the userâs pelvic floor muscles and translates the information to the âgameâ, allowing you to lift, pulse, or even hit moving targets on your phone.
The data collected is so sensitive that an LV score (a measurement in Newtons of the amount of force being applied to the pod) is fed to back to the user, allowing her to be aware of, and therefore altering the strength exerted by the pelvic floor muscles in her vagina (Elvie.com, 2017).
Comparing Elvie to what is traditionally regarded as SMART technology, it is similarly able to produce diagnostic reports, or âinstant bio feedbacksâ of oneâs pelvic floor muscles to its user. But while the tracker is the device producing the diagnostic reports, it is inevitably the vagina that labours, creating an environment for the tracker to then evaluate. The information collected is then transmitted to the bearer of the vagina, who uses the data to then decide whether or not to exert more or less force with her pelvic floor muscles.
Ultimately, it is the vagina that then adapts, labouring a modified version of itself in a cycle of human/machine dependent self-sustainability. Because of its active participation in this continuous loop of receiving and sending data, the latter definition of SMART technology â âcapable of learning, [âŚ] using experience to improve performance, anticipating, thinking and reasoning about what to do nextâ â is fulfilled, not by the tracker, but by the userâs vagina. Without the labour of the vagina, the tracker is unable to complete the cycle of data feeding and receiving in its entirety.
The occurrence of inter-dependent data production between technology and vagina therefore creates an effect whereby the definition of SMART technology is allocated to the vagina and its user, rather than the tracker, due to its ability to carry out and complete the function of adapting and improving performance. SMART technology developed for devices like the Elvie is consequently understood as yet another imagined route of feminized labour through which women are presented with the promise of self improvement, while preserving the illusion of autonomy and agency.
According to an article by elle.com promoting the pelvic floor exercise tracker,Â
âweakening of the pelvic floor can also have a negative effect on one's sex life [âŚ] When you strengthen this area, it is easier to get a tighter grip during sex, which makes for a more pleasurable experience for all parties involvedâ (Strauss, 2017).Â
Even with a list of long term health benefits like organ prolapse and urine leakage prevention, the Elvie persists to advertise with a strong emphasis placed on the benefits of increased vaginal sexual pleasure in women (Elvie.com, 2017).
While advocating for a more pleasurable sexual experience, the Elvie routinely excludes the discussion of the clitoris and the role it plays in delivering female pleasure. Choosing instead, to focus primarily on the vagina. Like in the case of hysteria treatments, vaginas continue to be viewed as the dominant route for sex and pleasure.
The Elvie renders its user a tool for self regulation, morphed into the gatekeeper of her own oppression, and reinforcing the same systematic patriarchal definitions of bodily fulfilment sustained in the 1800 â 1900s. It frames the vagina as the only viable route to improving the sexual or reproductive health of female bodies. What Foucault characterized as the âhysterisization of womenâs bodiesâ has thereby not been redefined, but instead, reoriented through SMART devices.
It seems the labouring vagina remains ubiquitous, even in the contemporary technological sense of today. Through the use of technologies like the Elvie, women are transformed into a mere device of capitalist, masculine intention â a SMART vagina â inevitably fused with the very resolution as the technology aimed at relieving its perceived limitations.
SMART Vaginas: Human or Non-Human?
The example of the Elvie explicitly outlines a diffusion between machine and body. As the device sits inside of the vagina, the distinction between what is ultimately embodied grows obscured. With the added cycle of data receiving, adapting of environment within the vagina of its user, and the subsequent feeding of information back to the machine, the division between female bodies and the functions of what characterizes SMART technology become inseparable.
The formation of SMART vaginas â neither machine, neither body; not adequately female, yet not male enough either â can therefore be recognized as the compounding of various dualisms: body and technology, human and non-human, physical and digital, feminized and masculinized, material and immaterial. The binary boundaries between what is prescribed agency and what isnât, what is imbued power as opposed to subjugation, and what ultimately is conceived in social reality becomes increasingly vague while examining these SMART technologies and their interactions with women.
The thresholds of utility between one blends into the other, and vice versa, becoming entangled within and between. They envelope layers of both gendered and technological discourses concurrently â the ubiquitous everywhere and everyWEAR, infused simultaneously with patriarchal intentions and capitalistic reproduction, turning women into neither human nor machines; simply as yet another endlessly labouring subject of unattainable outcome. Women live undeniably, and ubiquitously, both as human and machine; essentially as cyborgs, to which SMART vaginas are simply another symptom of.
One of the earliest descriptions of a cyborg was outlined in the 1960 issue of the journal Astronautics, "Cyborgs and Space" by NASA scientists Manfred Clynes and Nathan Klein. It was a term coined by them to describe a cybernetic organism: a human-machine hybrid capable of complementing the onset of space exploration. The word âcyborgâ was an amalgamation of the words âcyberneticâ and âorganismâ and was derived from the field of cybernetics, which delineated the discipline of feedback, control, and organism at the time.
Consistently cybernetic, its purpose was to create an environment that laboured a freedom from humanly limitations in order to enlarge and expand the human experience. Simultaneously melded with the meanings of organism, a cyborg was a being imbued with technological and mechanical properties that potentially coexisted, but were still considered mutually exclusive to one another.
âThe purpose of the Cyborg, as well as his own homeostatic systems, is to provide an organizational system in which such robot-like problems are taken care of automatically and unconsciously, leaving man free to explore, to create, to think, and to feelâ (Clynes, M.E. and Kline, N.S., 1995).
The cyborg was envisioned at the time as exclusively male, with a strong emphasis on leaving the world of freedom to explore, create, think, and feel, entirely for men. The cyborg of Clynes and Kleinâs imagining is therefore an entity of patriarchal consciousness. While women, in part excluded from the formation of its definition, and by omission, a contributor to its dream, become an unsuspecting labourer to the patriarchal masculine purpose of a cyborg.
While undoubtedly a cyborg herself â a body able to be lived in as well as apart from itâs mechanical conception, attached but still separable within the definition of what is cybernetic and what is organism â she continues to re-appropriate its purpose as one of the same. It thus disregards the politics and sociality of womanly consciousness for which it is a part of, unconsciously reproducing itself as an illusion of agency and autonomy. Clynes and Kleinâs cyborg therefore produced, in effect, what Sarah Kember reiterates as the ubiquitous paradigm of feminized labour in technology.
Donna Haraway and The Ubiquitous
Donna Haraway, a prominent contemporary scientific scholar, theorist, and feminist thinker, provides a more nuanced, and perhaps offers a more forgiving reality for cyborgs and the SMART vagina. She characterizes the cyborg as being entangled between human and machine, where the line between what is technology and what is human can no longer be so clearly distinguished. Unlike Clynesâ and Kleinâs, the purpose of which Harawayâs cyborg serves cannot be quite as easily outlined as well.
Haraway continues to expand on the failure to purpose a cyborg in the quote,Â
âmachines were not self-moving, self designing, autonomous. They could not achieve man's dream, only mock it. They were not man, an author to himself, but only a caricature of that masculinist reproductive dreamâ (Haraway,1991:10).Â
To her, cyborgs are not neutral subjects, unlike machines.
A thing like the SMART vagina produces in itself a masculinist âdreamâ â the perfectly functioning vagina â but simultaneously mocks it, as the perfect vagina is only as perfect as the machine that is able to produce one. In this definition, the âdreamâ is completely diminished, or eradicated, along with the premise that built it. Harawayâs cyborg thereby lives not within but between and around these âpromisesâ, suspicious of the very definition man aims to build of it.
SMART vaginas can therefore be interpreted under this very understanding as cyborgian entities that exist simultaneously as a creature of lived social reality, as well as a creature of fiction â just as Haraway imagines a cyborg to be. It is compounded by its many limitations of gendered and capitalist nature, concurrently an unrealistic imagining of a simply unachievable outcome.
Through the understanding of Harawayâs cyborg, we can also begin to interrogate the ambiguity of a SMART vagina as one that tears down the essentialist boundaries through which it is projected to exist, creating a framework that departs from essentialism and binaries, and replaces it with one that includes more porous feminist genealogies of technology, labour, body, gender, and capitalism within its discussion. It is Harawayâs cyborg that seeks to tear down the binaries and dualisms between the politicized male/female, feminine/masculine, human/non-human, and to depart from their patriarchal limitations. Essentially the genesis of a cyborg that lives out of a radical and feminist praxis.
Indeed, there is an expanded argument that occupies the masculine conception of technological approaches, as with the conception of the SMART vagina through ubiquitous devices described in earlier parts of this essay. Beginning with the description of the feminized labour of Janet Smart as a tool of subjugation within the technological world, to the unconscious hysterization of women, there is a ongoing discourse that supports the formation of feminized labour around and within the cyborgian woman as she exists within systems of masculine intention.
Such discussions of gender and feminist politics as it intersects and interacts with the technological realm of innovation and SMART should not be disregarded. All definitions between human and non-human get entangled and become crystallized in the making of a cyborg, and the making of the cyborg is certainly nuanced and complex.
However, the intention is not to suspend the discussion as iterated earlier, but rather, to embody Harawayâs vision of the future cyborg as one that can be built on top, or over that. I want to conceive of the SMART vagina not simply as a creature inescapable from the fact of a masculinized social reality, but one that can be reimagined to reject the very notions surrounding it.
In her seminal book, âCyborg Manifestoâ, Haraway describes the overlapping regions between technology and organisms:Â
âWe are all Chimeras, theorised and fabricated hybrids of machine and organism; inshort, we are cyborgs. Cyborgs are our ontologyâ. (Marciniak in Haraway,1991:1).Â
She displays an acknowledgement of the deeply-embedded existence of the non-human and human; that all social, political, and bodily functioning of the non-human and human are intwined within that of what we understand as reality. Haraway continuously dwells on ambiguity between the two by emphasizing the limits of what is perceived as natural and artificial, consequently redefining the cyborg as an entity that doesnât exist simply within binaries and dualisms, but rather, envelopes all.
The cyborg, according to Haraway, reconsiders rigid, hegemonic structures of what we understand as human and in turn, develops a characterisation of a post human cyborg that undermines these very structures. The breakdown of boundaries between stern categories like animal-human, organic-machine, and physical-nonphysical is what contributes to the formation of what she considers to be cyborg â inherently a disloyal and blasphemous subject. It is within Harawayâs theories that one may come to recognize the cyborg as non-linearly conceived, just as a SMART vagina isnât an innate product of nature or society either.
The SMART vagina reorganizes ideas about the cyborg as metaphor, but also restructures its history, social reality, and physical existence as entangled. It thus becomes embodied in an ephemeral space of conception instead. SMART vaginas are indeed inescapable as a subjugated figure; a product the masculine and patriarchal âdream, but it is also an evolving subject of the politics of body, society, gender, and feminism.
While it is recognized in Clynesâ and Kleinâs cyborg and SMART devices like the Elvie as occupying the techno-patriarchal dream of freedom and agency of female bodies; labouring unendingly in the pursuit of the goal of freedom and perfection, it is simultaneously in Harawayâs imagining of a cyborg that recognises the SMART vagina as persistently defiant â refusing a reproduction of the patriarchal dream, insofar as to mock it. The cyborg as embodied in the SMART vagina breaks down the implications of a biased, patriarchal system, and forms itself around the understanding of Harawarian cyborg instead. It is consequentially enmeshed and entangled in mechanical properties, while reproducing women and the vagina as a reimagined feminist, posthuman subject of technology and the future.
In âSimians, Cyborgs, and Womenâ Haraway elaborates that,Â
â[t]here is nothing naturally female that ties us together as womenâ (Haraway, D. and Teubner, U., 1991).Â
Everything created as âwomanâ is inherently part of systems of binaries created by masculinist and patriarchal forces, just as it is with the cyborg of feminized labour. While the conception of SMART vaginas seem to be one that outlines this âdreamâ, unconsciously producing a subjugated body of feminized labour, it is inevitably Harawayâs contextualising of a cyborg that allows for its porous qualities to be brought to focus. Replacing it in the realm of a âdreamâ and diminishing it as a masculine cyborg, and instead, as more of a Harawayan one.
The Future of SMART Vaginas and The Ubiquitous
The effect of machine and human merging is certainly not something that belongs exclusively to contemporary times. Evident during the hysterization period that occured in the 1800s â 1900s, cyborgs have always been part of the history of technology as it intersects with the politics of gender, taking on insidious roles in the lives of women through technological devices.
From hysteria to the ubiquitous, women have been engaging with the layered social and political dimensions of technology that evolved from medically administered and heterocentric treatments employed with vibrators, to the now ubiquitous use of SMART.
Today, technology still insists on telling women who we are, what we can be, what we can do with our bodies, and where we can go in the future. The existence of SMART vaginas, Elvies, and other devices that reiterate feminized labour have been permeating our human condition for a long time, and there is a framework that needs to be established for the gendered, feminist, and cyborgian discussions within it.
While Kember images the ubiquitous (Everywhere, and everyWEAR) within technology in the subjugation of women and the unconsciously labouring female bodies, Haraway imagines a human and non-human merging in a different light; one that mocks these hegemonic and heterocentric systems â a feminist cyborg counter-force.
The vision for a cyborgian future as described by Haraway is radical, non-linear, and calls for a porous landscape of existence. It is enmeshed within all encompassing definitions of science, nature, gender, and body, and thus a product of a posthuman world concerned not only with what binaries and dualisms are, but subsequently breaking them down, and embracing the various multiples that exist within it.
âFeminists re-appropriate science in order to discover and to define what is ânaturalâ for ourselves. A human past and future would be placed in our handsâ (Haraway, D. and Teubner, U., 1991).
Alas, both Kember and Haraway outline the importance of recognizing gender and feminist politics within the discourse of technological approaches. The SMART vagina should not remain uncontested as key to the genesis of discussions within cyborgian realities like emerging SMART technology and the ubiquitous. It is of cyborgian nature, and holds within that, the many interpretations of body/technology, human/non-human, physical/digital, feminized/masculinized, material/immaterial. It is entangled as part of the cyborg anthology that will pave the way for future feminists to understand gender politics within new technologies.
Devices such as the Elvie are becoming more readily available to women, and have the power to potentially perpetuate social beliefs of a certain gendered existence and patriarchal feminine subjugation.Â
Thus, we need to continue to be suspicious of the technological world while still remaining enthusiastic about what it can mean for us. We must continue to hold on to feminist genealogies that arenât engaged with and talked about enough, and to tear apart the ubiquitous. To engage in questions that of which technology brings with it â whose world is it making better? Ours or somebody elseâs?
If we are to achieve Harawayâs dream of a cyborgian existence, it is necessary to interrogate, recontextualize, and destroy the hegemonized language of technology that exists within the masculinised spaces. We must be attentive in refuting existing technologies that politicize gender, and redirect them into expanding categories of what is cyborg and what is posthuman. Undeniably, we need to continue to rebel and queer the techno realm of âfemaleâ work, and expand the future of work itself as they are set out in current debates of innovation and tech acceleration. Essentially, the furthering of feminist work.
Bibliography:
Clynes, M.E. and Kline, N.S., 1995. Cyborgs and space. The cyborg handbook, pp.29-34.
Davidson, A.I., 1987. How to Do the History of Psychoanalysis: A Reading of Freud's" Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality". Critical Inquiry, 13(2), pp.252-277.
Elvie.com. (2017). Your most personal trainer - Elvie. [online] Available at: https://www.elvie.com/ [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
Foucault, M., 1990. The history of sexuality: An introduction, volume I. Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage.
Freud, S. and Strachey, J., 1975. Three essays on the theory of sexuality (Vol. 5008). Basic Books.
Haraway, D., 1991. Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-Feminism in the Late Twentieeth Century. Simians, Cyborgs and women: The reinvention of nature, pp.149-181.
Haraway, D. and Teubner, U., 1991. Simians, cyborgs, and women (p. 203225). na.
Igi-global.com. (2017). What is Smart Technology | IGI Global. [online] Available at: http://www.igi-global.com/dictionary/smart-technology/38186 [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
Instagram.com. (2017). www.elvie.com (@hello.elvie) ⢠Instagram photos and videos. [online] Available at: https://www.instagram.com/hello.elvie/?hl=en [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
Kember, S. (2015). IMedia: The Gendering of Objects, Environments and Smart Materials. 1st ed. England: Palgrave Macmillan, p.81.
Kember, S., 2003. Cyberfeminism and artificial life. Routledge.
Maines, R.P., 2001. The technology of orgasm:" Hysteria," the vibrator, and women's sexual satisfaction. JHU Press.
Strauss, E. (2017). I Used a "Fitbit for the Vagina" and It Changed My Sex Life. [online] ELLE. Available at: http://www.elle.com/life-love/sex-relationships/a31308/elivie-kegel-exercise-app/ [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
Twitter.com. (2017). Elvie (@helloelvie) | Twitter. [online] Available at: https://twitter.com/helloelvie?ref_src=twsrc%5Egoogle%7Ctwcamp%5Eserp%7Ctwgr%5Eauthor [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
YouTube. (2017). Ubiquitous Women: Everywhere, Everywhere, and Everywear. [online] Available at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9VpDPTplGY4 [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
YouTube. (2017). re:publica 2015 - Sarah Kember: Sex, Lies and Smart Cities. [online] Available at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=w326aMfcZDQ [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
YouTube. (2017). Women Sync Their Vaginas To Their Smartphones. [online] Available at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=6GRwbiZSihA [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
Other readings:
Wired.com. (2017). Cite a Website - Cite This For Me. [online] Available at: https://www.wired.com/1997/02/ffharaway/ [Accessed 20 Apr. 2017].
Jones, M., 2017. Expressive Surfaces: The Case of the Designer Vagina.
Ahmed, S., 2010. The promise of happiness. Duke University Press.
https://www.refinery29.com/en-us/kgoal-loop-kegels-trackers
0 notes
Text
Revenge Sandwich week two
Iâm late, oops. This is going to be super rough, just a warning.
Villefort and Noirtier
I actually really love the relationship between these two. This is an amazing dynamic between two people who are ON THE OPPOSITE SIDES and yet still help each other and rely on each other and trust each other. How can I not love that? Even though I hate Villefort, and Noirtier doesnât seem like a great guy either.
The Second Restoration
HOW DOES EVERYBODY KEEP PREDICTING THAT ITâS GONNA HAPPEN? DUMAS STOP GIVING YOUR CHARACTERS SUPERNATURAL POWERS.
Also Iâm glad Dumas explains how Edmond wasnât released during the Hundred Days because I was wondering about that... except Iâm still not sure if I buy it. How did the jailers not react at all to Napoleon returning to power? This was a prison for political prisoners, wasnât it?
On the other hand, while I donât know if this is true but I do buy Napoleon being stricter about prison management than Louis XIV. That sounds about right. Because screw Napoleon.
The Villains
âVillefort shuddered at the idea of the prisoner cursing him in the darkness and silence.â GOOD. YOU SHOULD.
âFor Villefort, Marseille was full of memories that were soured with remorseâ AGAIN. GOOD.
Also something that came to my mind: I find it notable that even though it was a plot started by his peers, Edmond was ultimately ruined by an authority figure. This isnât just about villainous plots and revenge, itâs also about power and corruption. Same goes for what happens in the prison; the jailers abuse their power over him.
âDanglars knew fear. At every moment he expected Dantès to reappear, a Dantès who knew everything, a Dantès who was strong and who threatened every kind of vengeance.â YES GOOD. YOU DESERVE TO BE SCARED.
Same for Fernand.
MercÊdès and Papa Dantès
:(((((((
I do feel increasingly sympathetic towards Morrel tho. He seems like a good guy for a capitalist, despite how he was introduced.
Prison
Okay tbh most of what I have to say is just a lot of AAARGH and a LOT of hatred for the prison staff and the inspector and everybody involved. And I donât even know how Edmond survives this... and itâs hard to blame him for anything that comes after this because he went through hell to get to the Consumed By Vengeance stage. And Dumas does a good job at getting that across. âWhen I was still a manâ God, Edmond :( ALL OF THE HUGS, I WANNA GIVE THEM TO HIM.
âOf course,â the inspector remarked, with the naĂŻvety of the corrupt, âif he had really been rich, he would not be in prison.â
Oh snap
Faria and Edmond (under cut)
First I want to appreciate the scene where Edmond brings Faria news of Napoleonâs defeat that are already years old. Which just underlines just how isolated these characters are and how little the jailers tell them. It took years of digging to accidentally meet another prisoner so Faria could hear about the news. Not even the inspector bothered to say anything to him despite specifically noting that Fariaâs understanding of the political situation in Italy was outdated.
And itâs SUCH A RELIEF to have them meet finally. It was starting to get too painful to read about Edmondâs loneliness and Iâm actually shocked that Faria almost dismissed the chance to have some company. Itâs just so important for human beings to have at least some other living creature around.
Irrelevant side note: how the hell did Faria know anything about the surroundings of Château dâIf, much less the specific names of nearby islands?
Also I have trouble believing he seriously managed to do all the things he did in prison and never even ran out of soot for example or nobody wondered were all his shirt fabric kept disappearing etc. etc.
The part about being productive specifically because heâs in prison though... yeah, as an endless procrastinator I can definitely relate. Not that I want to go to prison just so I can be more productive mind you. :p
Fariaâs distaste towards killing seems very significant too. I was a bit shocked about how quickly Edmond was ready to jump to that option but then again it does seem consistent with his characterization. Itâs just not something Iâm used to with characters who are supposed to be innocent.
âwhile all handwriting written with the right hand varies, all that done with the left hand looks the same.â
I call bullshit, Dumas. This is actually one of the things that I remembered about this book. Really vividly even. I think it was because even as a kid I had a certain fascination with left-handedness and also even as a kid I called bullshit on this claim. :p
And again with the superpowers: Faria can somehow guess that there were two people plotting against Edmond despite Danglars being perfectly capable of executing the whole thing on his own.
Oh boy, revenge foreshadowing though...
The book sure went above and beyond to justify the treasure thing btw. :D And managed to tie it into historical events and all! I appreciate it.Â
âYou are my son, Dantès!â the old man cried. âYou are the child of my captivity. My priestly office condemned me to celibacy: God sent you to me both to console the man who could not be a father and the prisoner who could not be free.â
;__; <3
By the way, the way Edmond escapes was another thing that was foreshadowed already. I lost the specific line but Faria definitely said something about how successful escapes usually happen when you take advantage of an opportunity rather than careful planning. Thatâs exactly what Edmond ends up doing. Of course the work they did wasnât useless but it didnât free either of them until the opportunity came along. Even if it was the worst possible opportunity since it meant Fariaâs death.
(Sorry for the rushed post, this is the problem with reading ahead and then trying to remember all your thought about the thing later on... I made notes but notes only get you so far.)
5 notes
¡
View notes
Text
13 things that cannot happen under Capitalism (EXPLAINED!):
 Full employment
The end of poverty
World peace
Decolonization
Full equality of all social classes
A lastingly stable economy
Abolition/effective reformation of prisons/schools
Ethical consumption
Permacultural and fair global food system
Retirement of all senior citizens
Functional anarchy (looking at you, an-caps)
Free association
Direct democracy
0 notes