#what is mathematics
Explore tagged Tumblr posts
lvl10blvkmage · 4 months ago
Text
Tumblr media
oh no , the dog is drinking the wave equation
57K notes · View notes
introvertlifeee · 4 months ago
Text
Tumblr media
999 notes · View notes
2022dirt · 6 months ago
Text
Tumblr media Tumblr media Tumblr media Tumblr media
Random mathematics in public spaces.
647 notes · View notes
tanadrin · 29 days ago
Text
kind of have a pet peeve in popular science and science educational content where the presenter doesn't bother to look up and practice the pronunciation of long, unfamiliar technical terms and acts like it's just sooo impossible to figure out how to pronounce these words properly. dictionaries are free. the whole reason people are viewing this content is because they are interested in the subject. and i think in general the attitude "this thing is possible to learn and get conversant in" is more conducive to the act of learning and assimilating new information than "science is hard, of course you don't know anything, you little ditz you"
131 notes · View notes
hizerain · 2 months ago
Text
Tumblr media Tumblr media
2025.05.05
A mess of notebooks and papers. I've taken to organizing them in multiple piles across my floor. Somewhere slowly functionality over aesthetics has taken over life. My various fragile and beautiful fountain pens swapped for a sturdy indestructible rotring 600 ballpoint. Beautifully kept notebooks exchanged for loose sheets of paper flouncing around. To some extent, I do miss the enforced slowness of the other tools. At the same time, I've always had an aesthetic obsession which has often been suffocating. It has been nice to let go.
109 notes · View notes
boycaca · 11 months ago
Text
Yknow i get why scara is such a hater when it comes to childe because imagine you’re a 400+ year old puppet with your other immortal coworkers with their dark aesthetics and colors that all fit together in some way shape or form and then your boss decides to hire some 17 year old ginger kid just completely ruining the vibe. Like the color scheme isn’t actually that important i just think its funny but who is this cheerful human boy from a countryside village doing at our evil organisation meeting…. Shouldnt he be training with all the other grunts outside oorrr….
317 notes · View notes
Text
asked my professor what this ‘noodle-shaped thing’ on the chalkboard was in front of our 150 person class, thinking it was some fancy greek letter i didn’t know about
Tumblr media
turns out it was the number nine
146 notes · View notes
noelements-setempty · 4 months ago
Text
No, parents of the kid I tutor, I swear I didn't start telling your son about graph theory unprompted! He was the one who insisted on completing his multiple-choice matching question without crossing the lines over each other.
75 notes · View notes
louisplumpyass · 2 years ago
Text
Tumblr media
649 notes · View notes
vellichor-lover · 3 months ago
Text
Every time I feel like I hate my maths degree I just say to myself, “This is so Neil Josten core” and all the boredom evaporates from my body
81 notes · View notes
mumblesplash · 1 year ago
Text
something that’s been bugging me all day: how would you teach perspective drawing in a society that existed entirely within, say, a varied-gravity spaceship? so much of how we understand perspective is based on the existence of the horizon and our relationship to it. what if there’s no horizon? vanishing points as a concept depend on having a ground to be parallel or perpendicular to.
228 notes · View notes
fictionadventurer · 4 months ago
Text
It's a little crazy how much my philosophical worldview keeps boiling down to:
Everything is Cardinal's Map
Everything is Theology of the Body
Or to put it another way
The abstract exists and is beautiful and we as humans are constantly seeking it even if we can't sense it by material means
The abstract is reaching out to us and makes everything in our world a symbol for some greater meaning
Or to put it yet another way
There's a story beyond us
We are in the story
60 notes · View notes
Text
Okay, I went back to school shopping yesterday and got a green notebook for my literature class because literature felt like a pretentious green to me. I sent this to my partner with the added comment of math is red, but they responded with the fact that math is blue. My mom says that math is red, and my dad says math is blue. But here's the thing: both my mother and I hate math, and both my partner and my dad love math. So, theory, people who hate math think it's red, and people who love math think it's blue. Thoughts?
Reblog so that more people can see this poll I am so curious.
124 notes · View notes
thatsbelievable · 9 months ago
Text
Tumblr media
86 notes · View notes
laura1633 · 9 months ago
Text
If Red Bull's upgrades at COTA are not significant and Max has his hands tied because of the capabilities of the RB20 then Charles could end up playing a crucial role in whether Max becomes champion this year or not. The Ferrari has looked competitive recently in Charles' hands, if he can take a win or two then it will definitely help Max but if he starts splitting LN and Max it's going to really make things difficult for Max.
Btw this is not downplaying the fact that if Max is champion then it is purely on his merit given how amazingly he has driven this year. Hopefully you all know by now I would never downplay Max's talents! I am just thinking of the outright pace of the respective cars over the next few races and what could play out.
If Charles is going to be fast I am going to need him to be super fast so he is ahead of the Mclaren and not splitting the Mclaren and Red Bull. The end of the season is going to be interesting and will probably end up a significant time in Lestappen history - please let it be for positive reasons 🙏🏻
100 notes · View notes
catgirl-lucy · 6 months ago
Text
Ultrafilters & Ultrapowers
Hey! Call me Lucy. I might make an introduction blog later, but I first wanted to make a blog-post about ultrapowers.
Ultrafilters are a concept from set theory, I'll try my best to explain what they are and why they're defined as they are.
First, a quick overview of what we will do: we will extend the real number line by adding new numbers through the use of an ultrapower, these new numbers are called "hyperreals". Roughly, this means that we will have infinite sequences [a₀,a₁,a₂,...] of real numbers representing hyperreal numbers, where similar sequences are regarded as equal. We will also show a surprising theorem: although there are seemingly more hyperreals than reals, hyperreals look the same as real numbers "from within".
If we have a sequence of reals like this: [0,1,1/2,1/3,1/4,...] (I'll call this sequence "ε"), the hyperreal that it represents can be viewed as the "limit" of the sequence. Since a large number of entries of this sequence is smaller than any positive real number r > 0, ε will be smaller than any positive real number r, but since also a large number of entries is larger than 0, ε will be larger than 0. ε is thus an infinitesimal hyperreal number. This is mostly just intuition though, so don't worry if you don't entirely get it.
Two hyperreal numbers x = [x₀,x₁,x₂,...] and y = [y₀,y₁,y₂,...] are equal if x_i = y_i for a large number of indices i. But what does "large" mean in this context?
Well, that's where the ultrafilter comes in. Ultrafilters split a family of sets into sets that are "large" and sets that are "small". In this case, we split sets of natural numbers (numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, etc) into large sets and small sets, so we have an ultrafilter on ℕ, the set of natural numbers. Ultrafilters are identified by the family of large sets: if some set A is in an ultrafilter U, then it is large, and if it's not, then it is small.
We do want our notion of "large sets" and "small sets" to make sense: for example, a hyperreal should always be equal to itself, so we want the whole set of natural numbers, {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, ...} (which is the set of indices for which a sequence is equal to itself), to be large.
Obviously, it would make sense that if a set A is large and B is larger than A, then B is also large. Thus, if A ∈ U is a member of an ultrafilter U ("∈" is the membership symbol), and if B ⊃ A contains everything A contains too ("⊃" is the superset symbol), then B ∈ U is a member of the ultrafilter as well.
We also want hyperreal equality to be transitive, thus if [x₀,x₁,x₂,...] = [y₀,y₁,y₂,...] and [y₀,y₁,y₂,...] = [z₀,z₁,z₂,...], then we want [x₀,x₁,x₂,...] = [z₀,z₁,z₂,...]. If A = {i ∈ ℕ | x_i = y_i} is the set of points at which x and y are equal and B = {i ∈ ℕ | y_i = z_i} is the set of points at which y and z are equal, then C = {i ∈ ℕ | x_i = z_i}, the set of points at which x and z are equal, includes the set A ∩ B = {i ∈ ℕ | x_i = y_i ∧ y_i = z_i}, the set of points at which x is equal to y and y is equal to z. It thus makes sense to have our ultrafilter be closed under intersections: if two sets A and B are large, then the set of points that are both in A and in B, called the "intersection" of A and B (denoted A ∩ B), is a large set as well (and thus also in the ultrafilter).
It would also make sense that, if two hyperreal numbers are nowhere equal, then they aren't equal. So the empty set, {} = ∅, is small.
The five axioms above describe a filter:
A filter F on κ is a family of subsets of κ.
A filter F on κ must contain the whole set κ.
A filter F on κ must be upwards closed, thus for every large set A ∈ F, and every larger set B ⊃ A, B ∈ F is large as well.
A filter F on κ must be downwards directed, thus for every large set A ∈ F and every large set B ∈ F, the intersection of A and B, A ∩ B ∈ F, is large as well.
A filter F on κ may not contain the empty set.
However, these are the axioms of a filter, and not of an ultrafilter. Ultrafilters have one additional axiom.
Suppose we have the hyperreal [0,1,0,1,0,1,...]: an alternating sequence of 0's and 1's. Is this equal to 0 = [0,0,0,0,...], or to 1 = [1,1,1,1,...], or is it its own thing? (Note: the 0 in 0 = [0,0,0,0,...] is a hyperreal and the 0's in 0 = [0,0,0,0,...] are real numbers, so they're different (kind of) numbers both called "0"). If it is its own thing, then is it smaller than 1? If it is smaller than 1, then it must be smaller on a large set of indices, meaning it's equal to 0 on a large set of indices, meaning it's equal to 0. If it's not smaller than 1, well, it can't be larger, so it'd only make sense if it's equal to 1, but no axiom about filters says it should! That's why we have this last axiom for ultrafilters, which makes them "decisive": for every set A, it is either large (thus, A ∈ U), or small, meaning that its complement, Ac = {i | i ∉ A}, the set of all points that aren't in A, is large.
And so we have our six axioms of an ultrafilter:
An ultrafilter U on κ is a family of subsets of κ, these subsets are called "large sets".
κ is large.
U is upwards closed.
U is downwards directed.
∅ is not large.
For every set A ⊂ κ, either A ∈ U or Ac ∈ U.
But we're still missing one thing. We can take our ultrafilter U to be the set of all sets of natural numbers that contain 6. ℕ is large, as it contains 6. It is upwards closed: if A contains 6 and B contains everything that A contains and more, then B also contains 6. U is downwards directed: if both A and B contain 6, then the set of all points that are in both A and B still contains 6. The empty set does not contain 6, and every set either does contain 6 or does not contain 6. With this ultrafilter, two hyperreals x and y are equal simply when x₆ and y₆ are equal, so we don't get cool infinitesimals and infinities, and that makes me sad :(
These kinds of boring ultrafilters are called principal ultrafilters. Formally, a principal filter on κ is a filter F on κ for which there is some set X ⊂ κ so that any set A ⊂ κ is large only if it contains everything in X. This filter is often denoted as ↑X. If you want a principal filter U to be an ultrafilter, X needs to be a singleton set, meaning it only contains a single point x. Proving this is left as an exercise for the reader.
Let U be a non-principal ultrafilter on ℕ. This post is getting a bit long, so I won't show why such an ultrafilter exists. Now, we can take the ultrapower of ℝ, the set of real numbers, by U. This ultrapower is often denoted as ℝ^ℕ/U. Members of this ultrapower are (equivalence classes of) functions from ℕ to ℝ, meaning that they send natural numbers/indices to real numbers (the sequence [x₀,x₁,x₂,...] maps the natural number i to the real number x_i). These functions/sequences/equivalence classes are called hyperreal numbers. Two hyperreal numbers, x and y, are equal if {i ∈ ℕ | x(i) = y(i)}, the set of points at which they are equal, is large (i.e. a member of U). We can also define hyperreal comparison and arithmetic operations: x < y if {i | x(i) < y(i)} is large, (x + y)(i) = x(i) + y(i) and (x · y)(i) = x(i) · y(i). Every real number r also has a corresponding hyperreal j(r), which is simply [r,r,r,r,...] (i.e. j(r)(i) = r for all i).
In general, if M is some structure, κ is some set and U is some ultrafilter on κ, then we can take the ultrapower M^κ/U, which is the set of equivalence classes of functions from κ to M, where any relation R in M (for example, "<" in ℝ) is interpreted in M^κ/U as "R(x₁,...,xₙ) if and only if {i ∈ κ | R(x₁(i),...,xₙ(i))} ∈ U is large" and any function f in M (for example, addition in ℝ) is interpreted in M^κ/U as "f(x₁,...,xₙ)(i) = f(x₁(i),...,xₙ(i)) for all i ∈ κ".
A quick note on equivalence classes: in M^κ/U, points aren't actually functions from κ to M, but rather sets of functions from κ to M that are all equal on a large set of values. Given a function f: κ → M, the equivalence classes that f is in is denoted [f]. In this way, if f and g are equal on a large set of values, then [f] and [g] are actually just equal.
The hyperreal [0,1,2,3,4,...], which sends every natural number i to the real number i, is often called ω.
This part of the blog will get a bit more technical, so be warned!
In the beginning of this blog-post, I mentioned that hyperreals look the same as real numbers. I'll make this statement more formal:
For any formula φ that can be built up in the following way:
φ ≡ "x = y" for expressions x and y (expressions are variables and "a + b" and "a · b" for other expressions a and b)
φ ≡ "x < y" for expressions x and y
φ ≡ "ψ ∧ ξ" (ψ and ξ are both true) for formulas ψ and ξ
φ ≡ "ψ ∨ ξ" (ψ or ξ is true (or both)) for formulas ψ and ξ
φ ≡ "¬ψ" (ψ is not true) for an formula ψ
φ ≡ "∃x ψ(x)" (there exists a value for x for which ψ is true) for a variable x and an formula ψ
φ ≡ "∀x ψ(x)" (for all values of x, ψ is true) for a variable x and an formula ψ
We have that ℝ ⊧ φ (φ is true when evaluating equality, comparison and expressions from within ℝ, where variables can have real number values) if and only if ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ φ (φ is true when evaluating equality, comparison and expressions from within ℝ^ℕ/U, where variables can have hyperreal number values).
In other words: ℝ and ℝ^ℕ/U are elementary equivalent.
So, how will we prove this? Well, we will use induction: "if something being true for all m < n implies it being true for n itself, then it must be true for all n (where m and n are natural numbers)". Specifically, we will use induction on the length of formulas: we will show that, if the above statement holds for all formulas ψ shorter than φ, then it must also hold for φ.
However, we won't use the exact statement above. Instead, we will use the following:
Given a formula φ(...) and hyperreal numbers x₁,...,xₖ, ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ φ(x₁,...,xₖ) if and only if {i | ℝ ⊧ φ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} is large.
Now, why does this imply the original statement? Well, when k = 0, {i | ℝ ⊧ φ} can only be ∅ or ℕ. It being ∅ is equivalent to φ being false in ℝ and, if the statement is true, also equivalent to φ being false in ℝ^ℕ/U. And it being ℕ is equivalent to φ being true in ℝ and, again, if the statement is true, it is also equivalent to φ being true in ℝ^ℕ/U. We thus have that φ being true in ℝ is equivalent to φ being true in ℝ^ℕ/U.
Note: M ⊧ φ simply means that the formula φ is true when interpreted in M.
Now, why do we need this stronger statement? Well, it makes induction a lot easier: given that this statement holds for all ψ shorter than φ, it's easier to prove it also holds for φ.
Now, we can actually do the induction.
First, if φ ≡ "x = y", then we need to show that (1) ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ φ(x,y) iff (2) {i | ℝ ⊧ φ(x(i),y(i))} is large. This follows immediately from the definition of equality in ℝ^ℕ/U, the same holds for "<".
Now, if φ(x₁,...,xₖ) ≡ "ψ(x₁,...,xₖ) ∧ ξ(x₁,...,xₖ)", we have that {i | ℝ ⊧ φ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} = {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i)) ∧ ℝ ⊧ ξ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} = {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} ∩ {i | ℝ ⊧ ξ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))}. Since {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} is large iff ψ(x₁,...,xₖ) is true in ℝ^ℕ/U, and {i | ℝ ⊧ ξ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} iff ξ(x₁,...,xₖ) is true in ℝ^ℕ/U, and U is closed under intersections, we have that {i | ℝ ⊧ φ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} is large iff φ holds in ℝ^ℕ/U. A similar argument works for ∨.
If φ(x₁,...,xₖ) ≡ "¬ψ(x₁,...,xₖ)", then we can just use the ultraness of the ultrafilter.
If φ ≡ "∃y ψ(y,x₁,...,xₖ)", then {i | ℝ ⊧ φ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} = {i | ℝ ⊧ ∃y ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} = {i | ∃y ∈ ℝ. ℝ ⊧ ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} = ∪_{y ∈ ℝ} {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))}. We have that the set {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} for y ∈ ℝ is large iff ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ ψ(j(y),x₁,...,xₖ). If this set is large for some y ∈ ℝ, and thus if ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ φ(x₁,...,xₖ), then ∪_{y ∈ ℝ} {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} is larger than that set, so it is large as well. For the converse direction, if ∪_{y ∈ ℝ} {i | ℝ ⊧ ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i))} is large, then we can create a hyperreal z where ψ ⊧ ψ(z(i),x₁(i),...,xₖ(i)) for all i for which ℝ ⊧ ∃y ψ(y,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i)), and we have ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ ψ(z,x₁(i),...,xₖ(i)), and thus ℝ^ℕ/U ⊧ φ(x₁(i),...,xₖ(i)). Again, a similar argument works for ∀.
(Sorry if you couldn't follow along, I'm not good at explaining these things in an intuitive way.)
This result can be extended to show that M^κ/U is elementary equivalent to M for every structure M, every set κ and every ultrafilter U on κ.
Now, this result might be surprising, as we have a new number ω in ℝ^ℕ/U. Surely, there is a formula that states the existence of this number, right?
Well, it turns out, such a formula does not exist! You can try something like "there is no natural number n so that 1+...+1 w/ n 1's is greater than ω", but ω+1 is a natural number in the hyperreals, so such a natural number does exist. Similarly, any formula you can come up with, as long as it is created using the rules above (using conjunction, disjunction, negation, qauntification, etc), cannot state the existence of an infinite number ω.
But if ℝ^ℕ/U and ℝ are seemingly indistinguishable, might there already be an undetectable infinite real number in ℝ? Well, maybe~ :3 But it's undetectable anyways, so you don't have to worry about it.
Before I end this blog-post, I want to give some more intuition on what filters & ultrafilters actually are. To me, ultrafilters, and filters in general, are like "limits of sets". The principal filter ↑X has X as limit, while non-principal filters and ultrafilters have limits that aren't really sets, but look like ones. For example, you might have the set of prime numbers in your filter, and then the limit of that filter will be a "set" in which all numbers are prime numbers. And if your ultrafilter is non-principal (so for every n, there is a set A ∈ U in the filter that does not contain n), then the limit of that ultrafilter will be a "set" in which all numbers don't actually exist. In the case of filters, this "set" can be any "set" (though it still isn't really a set), but in the case of ultrafilters, this limit looks like a singleton set (i.e. it only has one "element": ω).
I don't know if my intuition of filters and ultrafilters will help anyone, tho, but I think it's cool!
That's all I had to say.
Bye!~ Have a nice day.
54 notes · View notes